The Journey’s End

Freedom’s Progress?: A History of Political Thought, by Gerard Casey

Casey closes his nine-hundred page overview with a summary, a signing-off, an explanation of why he took on this challenge.  It is a most excellent chapter.

You might have wondered on occasion why we should have bothered with so much old stuff?

Casey’s survey began with the dawn of man; his substantial focus on political though begins with ancient Greece, beginning perhaps 800 BC.  I only picked up the story with the chapter on Christianity, about 200 pages in; I will, at some point, read through the first chapters…how on earth is it that I skipped Aristotle and Plato?

In any case, Casey answers his own question: the Whig historians aren’t correct.  It isn’t so that things get better day after day, year after year.  It is a theme that Hans Hoppe recently spoke on extensively.  As you know, this is also my view.

Freedom’s Progre... Casey, Gerard Best Price: $71.31 Buy New $61.88 (as of 02:10 UTC - Details) Something to consider, perhaps: if we are to measure freedom’s progress in our material goods, we have never been more free than today.  Sure, there is room for improvement, but overall who can complain when compared to much of the rest of the world and certainly world history.  In other words, why bother with all of this libertarian kvetching?

I think the only reason to bother is moral; it is in the political philosophy where our freedoms have not progressed – in many ways regressed.

Casey offers an overview as to why he believes this: good ideas often aren’t taken up, an example of which he offers in Johannes Althusius (1563 – 1638).  Had Althusius’ idea of vertically arranged, interlocking but detachable entities with the foundation built on the family won out over Bodin’s idea of sovereignty residing at the top, 400 years of western history would have been quite different – and far more free.

The Middle Ages offer another example, with an almost infinite number of political and legal bodies competing under a moral framework of the Church.

…the authority of rulers was limited and the obligation of those who were ruled to offer obedience to that authority was conditional. …the king, as part of the community, was as bound by that law as anyone else. …there was a mutual exchange of promises between king and people…

The medieval Church played a vital role in checking the power of the king, providing a competing, overlapping authority to which an aggrieved could appeal.  The medieval Christian Church discovered the individual, made in the image and likeness of God; it was an individual who could find his freedom within the social and political framework of the time.

The Europe of today (or maybe the Europe of a century or two ago) is seen as a blending of Greek philosophy, Roman law and Christianity; the role of the political practices of the Germanic tribes is often overlooked despite playing at least as large a role in our freedom as any of these other contributors.

Casey notes the far-too-heavy and unjustifiable burden that many place on libertarianism; it is not the highest end in life, but only the highest political end.  He cites Rothbard, who offers: “Only an imbecile could ever hold that freedom is the highest or indeed the only principle or end of life.”

Contrary to what some critics of libertarianism suggest – that libertarians view their philosophy as the highest of all social values – Casey offers that it should be seen, instead, as the lowest; it is the most fundamental, a necessary condition if one is looking for an ordered life.

Yet here again there are critics – and rightfully so: there will be found libertarians who proclaim “anything peaceful,” as if anything peaceful will maintain order – order being a necessary condition if one is to maintain liberty.  Of course, libertarians do not advocate for limiting anything peaceful via force; yet we also need not glorify or be happy with the consequence of such a worldview.

I believe that a civilized existence requires both freedom and order. …The question isn’t really whether order is desirable; it is what kind of order is desirable, where that order is to come from and how that order is to be maintained.

Casey offers that for libertarians – just as for Althusius – genuine order rises intrinsically from the free interaction of individuals, and does not come extrinsically from on high. Casey leaves unsaid here, but I will suggest that this intrinsic order is built on a foundation that does come from on high – but not from man.

Althusius was attempting to design a political framework that would mimic the order of the Middle Ages without the benefit of a unified Church.  In that framework, the law worked because it was not legislated by man; it was the old and good law.  It was custom, refined by Christian ethics. Amazon.com Gift Card i... Buy New $25.00 (as of 06:10 UTC - Details)

Rothbard remarked that custom ‘must be voluntarily upheld and not enforced by coercion’ and that ‘people would be well advised (although not forced) to begin with a presumption in favor of custom…’

This is certainly so if one wants to maintain order, which is necessary if one wants to maintain liberty.  It also presents the difficulty for adherents of the non-aggression principle: if custom is valuable – even necessary – to maintain liberty, how is one to defend custom?

A method offered by Casey to defend and perpetuate this custom is through the family; unconsciously acquired cultural norms are passed along at an early age, development proceeds accordingly.  Burke would say that these norms, the necessary foundation, are manners.

If such norms are not developed when young, it is not likely that they will be developed through the intellect when an adult.  When it comes to the family and the State, it is clear that everything possible is done to subsidize family-destroying actions.  Perhaps we libertarians need not wonder why very few people respond to our rational libertarian arguments.

Many libertarians argue that such cultural norms are encumbrances placed on us in violation of the non-aggression principle.  Dostoevsky’s Grand Inquisitor chapter fromThe Brothers Karamazov is offered in reply: such encumbrances choose us before we choose them; there is no “mythical free and autonomous self that exists apart from these ties.”

Granted, this is more of an Orthodox – rather than Western – idea of freedom; however, it was Orthodox in the West perhaps prior to the Renaissance, and most certainly prior to the Enlightenment.

Ralph Wood suggests that our freedom resides in freely embracing these moral, religious and political obligations.  Hard to stomach, I know.  But what if living within cultural norms is necessary for liberty?  Would a libertarian then embrace this?  Based on what chain of reasoning derived from the non-aggression principle?  Or do we require something more if it is liberty that we are after?

Conclusion

I am on quite safe grounds to suggest that Western society has lost this idea of order coming from cultural norms.  I am also on safe grounds to suggest that the relationship between this loss of cultural norms and man-made legislation and regulation is almost perfectly inversely correlated.

For us to find liberty – as measured in a reduction in man-made legislation and regulation – we might consider the value in supporting, once again, the cultural norms from which our liberty came.

Whether these societies can replenish their social capital is a matter for conjecture.  Some societies have done so in the past – but others have not, and have perished.

I am on quite safe grounds to suggest that there will be no freedom to be found in that.

Reprinted with permission from Bionic Mosquito.