Who Writes History?

Libertarians have been heartened in the past few years due to the great growth of their philosophy, especially thanks to the influence of Ron Paul, Lew Rockwell, and others associated with the Mises Institute. However, libertarians are still a tiny minority, really a remnant. This is especially true among historians with the notable exceptions of Tom DiLorenzo and Tom Woods making the rule. What is noteworthy is that the libertarian can learn much from the good non-libertarian historians, albeit reading with a libertarian perspective (this concept will be expanded upon below) to put the facts in context.

It is in this spirit that I recommend the book Who Speaks for the River: The Oldman River Dam and the Search for Justice by Robert Girvan.  (Note that Robert is a friend of my family, our wives went to school together as children in France.)  This book tells the history of a dam in southern Alberta, Canada from the perspective of the Native people (the Piikani Nation of the Blackfoot Confederacy) and environmentalists who were against the construction, and the farmers and government officials who supported it.  The history concerns the European incursions into the territory, treaties and agreements between the Canadian government and the Piikani including [amazon asin=192708301X&template=*lrc ad (right)]water rights, and finally the dam project itself that led to a Native protest that attempted to divert the path of the river.  The leader of this protest, Milton Born With A Tooth, was arrested for shooting over the heads of the police to warn them that they were trespassing on Piikani land. The book follows his two trials that resulted in him being convicted and sent to prison.

Girvan is a former crown prosecutor in Canada who writes from an in-the-know perspective about legal issues and with an almost naiveté in the ways of the world.  I can say from personal experience that he is a very nice person. He is absolutely fair to every participant. With the evidence he provides Girvan could easily have brought an indictment against the Conservative government of Alberta, but didn’t.  I am sure he would never condemn government per se.  He believes government through the rule of law is the source for justice in the world, not the tool for control it is in practice as he documents so well in this history.

This book illustrates practical and theoretical issues of libertarian interest.  He recounts dozens of examples of the nature; i.e., the perfidy, of government. For example, take this comment from inside the state.

Lorne [Fitch, a government biologist] told me the government didn’t want to know the truth.  He remembered one time when a biologist’s report containing unpleasant truths vanished into government and never surfaced.  When he began working for the government, the political portion of the civil service was at the very senior levels of government.  As time passed, the political dimension began to creep down.  More and more employees’ jobs and output were directly related to political leanings, which meant that Alberta’s was not a dispassionate, disaffected, stand-alone civil service.  As time passed, the number of people employed by the communications division of Alberta’s Ministry of the Environment made that ministry the largest in the Alberta government.  As Lorne later said, “So anything that comes out of government, even a status report on species at risk, is vetted through that Ministry of Truth.”

Statements and analysis on the nature of the law and the bureaucracy occur over and over again.

The lawyer with the Government of Alberta who had the unenviable task of dealing with this issue was Bruce Fraser, director of the Special Prosecutions Branch of the Alberta government’s Attorney General’s office. The Attorney General’s office in every government has a unique role.  On the one hand, their lawyers are supposed to prosecute cases independent of political power and influence.  Usually in Canada, in my opinion, prosecutions are conducted in this fashion.  This is a true achievement of our legal system, though of course it is not perfect, and we must always be vigilant.  On the other hand, the Attorney General’s office is run by the Attorney General, in this case, part of the ruling Conservative Government of Alberta.  Needless to say, the tension inherent in enduring a prosecution on an important project must have filtered down to the lawyers within the Attorney General’s office. (This is my educated speculation, rather than the product of inside knowledge.)

At the end of Judge Harvie’s decision, he raised a point that only radicals mention, and even then quietly (at least in Canada). He wondered if the Provincial Court of Alberta was independent enough of the political power of Alberta to even decide the case; …

Joanne [Helmer, a local journalist] suggested that [Jim] Horseman’s [deputy premier of Alberta] comments about the Oldman Dam being “vital to the economic survival of the whole of southern Alberta” were “nothing more than the attempt to create hysteria among the southern Albertans so they will support the provincial government’s decision to continue construction of the dam in the face of a federal appeal court decision to quash the earlier federal approval of the project.

One high-level civil servant explained to Joan Ryan [an anthropologist] how the Department of Indian Affairs worked: “It is indicative of the way the bureaucracy works to serve personal ends. You must remember, to finance officers and others at headquarters who have never served at the field level, the Indian people are invisible and not very real, so it is easy for selfish personal reasons to take precedence.

A real appreciation for the power of propaganda comes from Martha Kostuch, the staunch environmentalist in the story who brought several suits against the Alberta government for violating the law in starting the project without a permit.  Even she “did not believe that the Alberta government lawyers she dealt with in her struggle behaved improperly; they were simply following orders.”

Early in the book Girvan asks, “Did building a dam make economic sense?” Kevin Van Tighem, a writer and conservationist from Alberta, testified to a commission studying the project that “A decision to build this dam in spite of common sense was a political decision—a tangible, high-profile way of spending public deficit dollars in the south while signalling a commitment to water supply…We have a water welfare state in southern Alberta masquerading as a proud, conservative, self-sufficient society … Water metering and fair pricing to rationalize water demand in irrigation districts” could be implemented.  From an Austrian economics perspective we know that the more than 300 million dollars for a few hundred farmers would never make sense if spent by the government because economic calculation, without profit and loss, is impossible by the state.

At one point Girvan indicates that he recognizes the important questions regarding the economic back story.

Powerful forces worked tirelessly to promote the dam.  The issue wasn’t just water but also big money.  Water has a tendency, at least in human society, to flow toward poser and money, until the power and money wane.  Hundreds of millions of dollars in contracts and water-fuelled money were to be made; and political careers would advance by landing the water and money.  Of course, more noble motivations—having jobs and a thriving community for the next generation—must also have been present.

But this line of inquiry, naming the names of the powerful forces, is not followed up.[amazon asin=1933550279&template=*lrc ad (right)]

A fundamental aspect of the history is the property rights of the Native People as opposed to the state and others.  From a libertarian perspective we can look to Murray Rothbard who provides a theory for the assigning of property rights in Man, Economy and State:

Furthermore, in the question of land, it is difficult to see what better title there is than the first bringing of this land from a simple unvaluable thing into the sphere of production.  For that is what the first user does. He takes a factor that was previously unowned and unused, and therefore worthless to anyone, and converts it into a tool for production of capital and consumers’ goods. While such questions as communism of property will be discussed in later parts of this book, it is difficult indeed to see why the mere fact of being born should automatically confer upon one some aliquot part of the world’s land. For the first user has mixed his labor with the land, while neither the newborn child nor his ancestors have done anything with the land at all.

Thus, by libertarian justice if not law, do the Piikani people own the land and water where they had lived for centuries before the Europeans arrived? I think it is not clear in that they did very little to convert it into a tool for production of capital and consumers’ goods.  But can that be the sole criterion? Is the land truly “worthless to anyone” without improvement? I would disagree; and therefore, believe the Piikani had rights.

The key historical event was the signing of the treaty that in effect indicated that the Canadian government believed that the Piikani has rights to the land.

Canada and the Blackfoot “signed” a treaty—called Treaty 7—at Blackfoot Crossing, in September 1877, after many days of negotiations.  It is clear now that neither side understood the other; how much true communication there was remains an open question.  For many years, in the English language, what passed for a history of the treaty was based on newspaper accounts, the written treaty itself, and the report of Canada’s chief negotiator, David Laird.  The Blackfoot point of view did not exist in English until such scholars as Hugh Dempsy tried to bring it forward.  When I asked Piikani ceremonialist Reg Crowshoe about the treaty, he said that the Piikani had not intended to go to the negotiations, until the police found them at a place called O’Agency—where the Oldman and the Crow Lodge rivers meet—pointed a cannon at their camp, and told them to “get up to the treaty, or we’re going to blow the whole camp right out of the Oldman River valley;”

From this description you can imagine why “another member of the tribe said, ‘Treaty 7—that’s when the swindle started.’” A contract signed under threat of violence and false pretenses can certainly be considered unjust, even if it is considered legal by the law of those perpetrating the swindle.

The history of persecutions and swindles of the Piikani continued after the treaty until the confrontation over the dam project.  During the trial of Milton Born With A Tooth his lawyer made the case for ownership.

Remember, the Peigans [the name for the local native band] didn’t know what was happening.  All they saw, and I mean this quite seriously, was something like a small military invasion.  The police testified that they had brought a helicopter, dozens of officers, dozens of vehicles, and heavens knows how many guns to enforce an injunction against six, eight, ten people? The police had no right to treat the diversion site as an armed camp…. The police assumed they can do whatever they like on private property….These kind of assumptions invariably mean the use of power and strike at the freedom of all of us.  The police have to respect the laws as much as you or I do.

In contrast the prosecutor stated the government’s position.

We know that the land that they were on does not belong to the Indian band nor does it belong to the federal government or the Department of Indian Affairs.  The land they were on belonged to the Alberta government who had access to the land by way of a permit from the federal—[amazon asin=0945466366&template=*lrc ad (right)]

I read this book under the guidance of Ludwig von Mises, who explained why history needs theory to be comprehensible in Epistemological Problems of Economics.

History cannot be imagined without theory. The naive belief that, unprejudiced by any theory, one can derive history directly from the sources is quite untenable. [Heinrich] Rickert has argued in an irrefutable way that the task of history does not consist in the duplication of reality, but in its reconstitution and simplification by means of concepts. If one renounces the construction and use of theories concerning the connections among phenomena, on no account does one arrive at a solution of the problems that is free of theory and therefore in closer conformity with reality. We cannot think without making use of the category of causality. All thinking, even that of the historian, postulates this principle. The only question is whether one wants to have recourse to causal explanations that have been elaborated and critically examined by scientific thought or to uncritical, popular, prescientific “dogmas.” No explanations reveal themselves directly from the facts. Even if one wanted to draw conclusions uncritically— post hoc, ergo propter hoc—one would be completely at a loss in view of the confusing plethora and diversity of phenomena.  It is precisely the “multifarious causal complexity” of processes of which [Karl] Muhs speaks, i.e., the concurrence in them of a multiplicity of causal factors, that makes theory necessary.

So what theories or concepts can we use to understand this history?  First is the importance of property rights in understanding the history, law, and ethics of the Piikani relations with Canada.  I might speculate further that a cultural respect for property rights is a necessary condition for a stable civilization.  The Piikani have learned the hard way that they must take ownership of their culture to preserve it.[amazon asin=B0090ABXV6&template=*lrc ad (right)]

We can also discern the nature of government from this history. Franz Oppenheimer made the classic observation the Political and Economic means of survival.

There are two fundamentally opposed means whereby man, requiring sustenance, is impelled to obtain the necessary means for satisfying his desires. These are work and robbery, one’s own labor and the forcible appropriation of the labor of others.

So to speak of government is to speak of robbery, criminals and criminality.  From Wikipedia we can find a definition for organized criminal activity.

Organized crime, and often criminal organizations are terms which categorize transnational, national, or local groupings of highly centralized enterprises run by criminals, who intend to engage in illegal activity, most commonly for monetary profit.

Other organizations—including states, militaries, police forces, and corporations—may sometimes use organized crime methods to conduct their business, but their powers derive from their status as formal social institutions.

I love the second phrase that makes the point that there is not much real difference between organized crime and government. I would differentiate government from organized crime by the use of indoctrination by government; that is, government is a specialized subgroup of organized crime.  Bringing the themes of property rights and government together, I have written my own definition of government based on its fundamental nature and activities.

The organized transfer of wealth, typically but not always within a territory, through the systematic violation of property rights; always with the use or imminent use of violence, but often with indoctrination and/or the deception of individuals to achieve a voluntary transfer.

With this concept understood Robert Girvan’s history of the dam is easily understood.  During an interview with a participant in the protest, Girvan wondered why the Alberta government was so determined to build the dam. The response is priceless and should be remembered when trying to understand every government action.

You’ve got to expand your mind.  Follow the money.  Follow the money. Think of what this water is worth….